Some Thoughts Towards a Theory of
Musical Ekphrasis
Siglind Bruhn
1 Art about Art?
"...il y a de bizarre, et même
d'inquiétant, dans le fait d'une inspiration de seconde main,
cherchée dans les oeuvres d'autrui, et cherchée dans un
art dont les buts et les moyens sont très différents de
ceux qui charact‚risent l'art poétique. Est-ce vraiment
légitime? Est-ce vraiment utile et fécond?"
[Étienne Souriau, La poésie française et la
peinture (London 1966), p. 6]
|
"...there is something odd, and even disturbing, in
second-hand inspiration, sought in the works of someone else, and
sought in an art form of which the aims and the means are very
different from that which characterize poetry. Is this really
legitimate? Is this truly useful and fruitful?"
|
There are various ways in which one art form
can fruitfully relate
to another. Coexistence is much more frequent--and apparently much
less disturbing for an audience--than the declared attempt at a
"transformation" or new representation in another sign system. Does
this "second-hand inspiration," as Souriau called it, constitute a
genuine creative act? To overemphasize what seems to be his question:
is there a risk that the "representation of a representation" might
suck the blood and life force from the first work, or to come out as
a merely derivative, bloodless response? What do artists mean when
they say that the new work can be cherished alone but fully
understood and appreciated only in light of the earlier work on which
it reflects?
When composing his piano cycle Gaspard
de la nuit, Ravel
not only chose for his three pieces the titles of three of Bertrand's
poems, but actually reprinted each poem on the page facing the
beginning of the musical piece that refers to it. While Ravel's music
is no doubt beautiful and self-sufficient when appreciated without
knowledge of the literary source (as is usually the case in today's
concert practice), the listeners' insight into the depth of the
musical message increases dramatically once the music is comprehended
in light of the poem.
Let me briefly recall the central piece, Gibet.
Bertrand,
in asking us to witness the death of a hanged man, draws our
attention to two facets of a transitional space. On the one hand,
there is the very moment between life and death; the two framing
verses clearly stake out this ground. The question that pervades all
six stanzas of his poem asks after the origin and nature of a
sound--a sound that, after having been suspected to come from the man
himself or from the insects that surround his head, turns out to be
the tolling of the death-knell. At the beginning, the lyrical "I" is
wondering whether the sound may be the sigh of the hanged man; there
may still be life. But the end speaks unequivocally of a carcass, a
corpse. The entire poem can thus be read as an unfolding of that
moment between almost-no-life and definite death. On the other hand,
Bertrand elicits, in the four central stanzas, the interaction
between the living and the not-quite-dead. Significantly, the
creatures proposed as possible sources of the puzzling sound are not
animals whom a man could look in the eye, but
insects--representatives of transition. Cricket, fly, beetle, and
spider all relate to the hanged man in ways that evolve from the
innocuously disinterested to the downright morose.
Ravel captures many of the nuances expressed
through Bertrand's
poem in his piano piece. As in the poem, the tolling of the bell is
the unifying feature. The tolling never pauses and never changes its
pitch. Its rhythm, however, makes it clear that all is not in order
here. Against this incessant sounding of the death-knell, Ravel
proceeds to lay out his melodic material which, in four ever more
emotionally loaded steps, moves further and further away from any
meaningful relationship to the central scene and the dignity we
expect in the context of a death-knell. In the image drawn by
Bertrand, this musical development corresponds with the increasingly
disrespectful way in which the creatures of transitional space relate
to the hanged man. While Ravel's piano piece is undoubtedly beautiful
when heard as absolute music without any connection to an
extra-musical stimulus, the listener gains access to its full depth
only when appreciating it as a transmedialization of Bertrand's
poem.
2 Musical Ekphrasis in Intermedial
Space
As the brief description shows, Ravel's
piano cycle on Bertrand's
poems in no way constitutes vaguely impressionistic "program music."
Instead, this is a case of a transformation of a message--in content
and form, imagery and suggested symbolic signification--from one
medium into another. For this phenomenon we seem to lack a specific
term; I will make a case for calling it "the musical equivalent to
ekphrasis." Not surprisingly given the lack of a distinctive term, no
methodology seems to have been developed that would allow us to
differentiate within what I will argue is a unified and highly
sophisticated genre, or to define the genre within the larger fields
in which it is situated.
These fields can be imagined as surrounding
musical ekphrasis,
linked to it at various points of interaction or by way of the
questions asked in aesthetic theory about assumptions underlying all
of them. (In the graphic overview I single out two of music's sister
arts--painting and literature--to stand for what is of course a much
richer texture of interactions, encompassing not only other forms of
visual art but also dance and mime as well as many hybrid forms of
artistic expression. By the same token, the aesthetic theories that
question musical ekphrasis with regard to its concepts, touch on many
more issues than the few that I have listed in the diagram.)
Among the possible pairings between two art
forms that express
themselves in different sign systems (verbal, pictorial, sonic,
kinetic, etc.), the relationship between words and images is the one
that is most widely explored. And in fact, the most securely
established terminology is found in a field that has experienced a
significant revival in recent years: ekphrasis or, more
particularly, ekphrastic poetry: poems inspired by paintings or other
works of visual art, including etchings and drawings, sculptures and
architecture, photographs, films, etc. The field is amazingly broad
and varied both historically and geographically. In his three-volume
study Das Bildgedicht, the German scholar of ekphrasis,
Gisbert Kranz, lists 5764 authors of ekphrastic poetry representing
thirty-five languages and twenty-eight centuries (from Homer to our
days)! Altogether fifty thousand poems on visual art are referenced
in his 1500-page bibliography. James Heffernan in his seminal book of
1993, Museum of Words: The Poetics of Ekphrasis from Homer to
Ashbery, defines ekphrasis as "the verbal representation of
visual representation"; Claus Clüver, in his 1997 article
"Ekphrasis Reconsidered: On Verbal Representations of Non-Verbal
Texts," expands the definition fortuitously to "the verbal
representation of a real or fictitious text composed in a non-verbal
sign system."(FN1)
The musical equivalent of ekphrasis
is a much more recent
phenomenon. Moreover, the first examples of the budding new genre,
written in the last years of the 19th century, were mostly not
distinguished from the broader category of "program music."; Musical
compositions with explicit reference--whether verbal in titles and
accompanying notes or onomatopoeic--have existed for much of the
history of Western music; yet, I claim, musical ekphrasis has
not.
3 Musical Ekphrasis versus Program Music
This brings me to an important task in
approaching the subject
matter of this study, that of defining the criteria along which we
can agree to distinguish between musical ekphrasis on the one hand
and what is generally known as "program music" on the other. The two
genres belong to the same general species: both denote purely
instrumental music that has its raison d'être in a
definite literary or pictorial scheme; both have variously been
described as "illustrative" or "representative" music.While the term
"program music" is considered by many to be simply the umbrella term
for both kinds, I will argue that it is not only meaningful, but
essential for a full understanding of music of the "ekphrastic" kind
to attempt a distinction.
In literature, the equivalent is the
distinction between ekphrasis
proper and "word painting" or "Beschreibungsliteratur." One way of
approaching the difference is to ask whose fictional reality is being
represented. "Program music" narrates or paints, suggests or
represents scenes or stories (and, by extension, events or
characters) that may or may not exist out there but enter the music
from the composer's mind. The range of application for the term
"program music" is wide, spanning from the biographical (Strauss's
Aus Italien) and the emotional expression associated
with
nature near or far (from Beethoven's "Erwachen heiterer Gefühle
bei der Ankunft auf dem Lande" in the Pastoral Symphony to
Holst's The Planets) through the depiction of an historical or
literary character (Berlioz's King Lear, Liszt's Hamlet) all
the way to a musical impression of a philosophically created "world"
(Strauss's Also sprach Zarathustra).
The musical equivalent to ekphrasis, by
contrast, narrates or
paints a fictional reality created by an artist other than the
composer of the music: a painter or a poet. Also, ekphrastic
music usually relates not only to the content of the poetically or
pictorially conveyed fictional reality, but also to the form and
style of representation in which this content was cast in its primary
medium.
The generous grouping and lack of
distinction between program
music and musical ekphrasis affected composers as well as listeners
and scholars. Composers, particularly at the beginning of the 20th
century when "program music" was gaining a bad reputation in
comparison to "absolute" or "pure" music, often obfuscated their full
intent in the hope to be taken seriously. Such concealment happened
not only with programs of the more general kind (one is reminded of
Mahler's withdrawing his poetic outlines for his symphonies), but
also and particularly in the case of music based on extant works of
art. Thus Schoenberg originally denied that his Pelleas und
Melisande was more than only vaguely inspired by the topic of
Maeterlinck's Symbolist drama, acknowledging only decades later how
exact a "transformation"; he had actually tried to achieve here. The
fact that listeners and scholars were discouraged from making a
distinction between the two adjacent categories of music resulted in
a considerable delay between the first occurrence of the phenomenon
of musical ekphrasis and its proper recognition.
I am interested in finding an answer to the
question what it may
mean if composers claim to be inspired by a poem or painting, a drama
or sculpture, and to have transformed the essence of that art work's
features and message, including their personal reaction to it, into
their own medium: the musical language. I expect to find as many
responses to the challenge of interartistic transformation as there
are works in the genre. Thus, while my investigations will be guided
by the search for a methodological framework within which all such
transpositions find their place, I admit that my fascination with the
variety of approaches taken and solutions developed overrides my
interest in the grid on which I may eventually lay them out.
4 Attempt at an Analog Definition
When pursuing the above-mentioned question
what exactly we mean
when we talk about a transmedialization of a work of literature or
art into music, I begin with the assumption that the creative process
that applies in the step from a painting to its poetic rendering can
usefully be compared to that which leads from a poem or painting to
its rendering in music; in fact I maintain that they correspond to a
degree that justifies adapting the terminology developed in the
adjacent field.
In view of this wider application, I would
thus like to offer a
third definition of ekphrasis which further generalizes Claus
Clüver's wording. Ekphrasis in this wider sense would then be
defined as "a representation in one medium of a real or fictitious
text composed in another medium." As I understand it, what must be
present in every case of ekphrasis is a three-tiered structure of
reality and its artistic transformation:
(1)
|
a scene or story--fictitious or real,
|
(2)
|
a representation of that scene or story in visual form
(a painting or drawing, photograph, carving, or sculpture (or, for that
matter, in film or dance;(FN2) in any mode that reaches us primarily
through our visual perception), and
|
(3)
|
a rendering of that representation in poetic language.
|
The poetic rendering can and should do more
than merely describe
the visual image. Characteristically, it evokes interpretations or
additional layers of meaning, changes the viewers' focus, or guides
our eyes towards details and contexts we might otherwise overlook.
Correspondingly, what must be present in every case of what I will
refer to as "the musical equivalent to ekphrasis" is
(1)
|
a scene or story--fictitious or real,
|
(2)
|
its representation in a visual or a verbal text, and
|
(3)
|
a rendering of that representation in musical language.
|
5 Depiction and Reference
Expanding from here, I wish to argue that
what and how music
communicates about any extra-musical stimulus falls into two
categories that can be seen as analogous with those pertinent in the
context of painting and poetry, namely, depiction and reference. I
will use depiction by musical means as encompassing not only
instances of mimicry, but also, and more importantly, emotions and
feelings. Correspondingly, reference by musical means, just like
reference by verbal and pictorial means, will be understood as
relying on cultural and historical conventions. In this context,
Leonard Meyer speaks of connotations, which he defines as "those
associations which are shared in common by a group of individuals
within a culture." Thus, he continues, "[c]onnotations are
the result of the associations made between some aspect of the
musical organization and extramusical experience."(FN3)
In music, a representation of "the extant
world" is not quite so
obvious. Schopenhauer objects fervently to the notion of musical
imitations of "phenomena of the world of perception,"(FN4)
and Tovey concurs with so many musicologists of his time who maintain
that programmatic elements in "serious" music are irrelevant to its
value as music.(FN5) One believes that music
has only very limited mimetic potential, while the other declares any
musical representation as undesirable. This was not always the
dominant view. Rousseau when writing his Dictionnaire de
musique in the 18th century clearly did not think so. Under the
heading "imitation" he included two entries, apparently conflating
"mimesis" and "imitatio." The second entry deals with the expected,
technical device of "the same aire, or one similar, in many parts,"
while the more prominent first entry explores the field of music
imitating things extra-musical, clearly arguing that this art is no
less capable of emulation than its sister arts.
Conventions established between the parties
engaging in
communication through representation need not, and in fact do not,
end with verbal language. The musical language--our primary concern
in this study--has developed a highly sophisticated catalogue of
signifiers that are agreed, within our cultural tradition, to be
understood as "pointing towards" non-musical objects. Among the most
well-known are
(1)
|
the semantic interpretation of brief musical units its
representation in a visual or a verbal text, and as "gestures" on the
basis of their kinesthetic shape,(FN6)
|
(2)
|
the figures of musical rhetoric developed in the 15th
and 16th centuries,
|
(3)
|
the retracing of a visual object (like the Cross) in
the pitch outline, and
|
(4)
|
the letter-name representation of or allusion to
persons--from Bach's famous pitch signature and those of Schumann,
Shostakovich,(FN7) Schoenberg, Berg, Webern,
etc. to the acrostic bows of reverence to a patron (Schumann's ABEGG)
or a lover (Berg's HF).
|
These four basic categories actually
constitute intrinsically
different ways of music's "referring to" a non-musical object.
Rhetorical figures, while modeled after (verbal) oratory, do not rely
on a mediator to be understood by those familiar with them; they
function almost like a semantic vocabulary. Gestures need
Einfühlung on the part of the individual listener,
who
perceptively links a certain structure with a kinesthetic image to
arrive at an affective connotation. Suggestive pitch contours are
(usually clumsy) translations of visual silhouettes and represent an
object only insofar as the listener attaches the (metaphoric)
concepts of "high" and "low" to what is heard as faster or slower
vibration;(FN8) and letter-name allusions
rely on the prior translation of the musically received message into
its notational equivalent and its basically arbitrary, though
conventionally prescribed alphabetic signifiers in order to be
decodable.
Yet even the latter two cases of mediated
representation can turn
into convention. The listeners' experience of a correlation between
certain musical tropes and implied meanings develops from unexpected
recognition--or the recognition of unexpectedness(FN9)
--via repeated exposure to anticipation, thus establishing a set of
conventions that may gradually come to bypass the original mediator,
even develop into forms where the mediator is actually inaccessible.
Similarly, the Germanic naming of pitches (with B and H as well as
the suffix-inflected Fis for F# and Es for Eb) is self-evident
neither for the Romance-language terms for pitches, which are based
on do-re-mi and modified by idiosyncratic words for "sharp"
and "flat," nor for the Anglo-Saxon scale lettered A-B-C-D-E-F-G. As
a consequence, it is a matter of learned convention, and thus of the
"joy of literacy," if lovers of Western music across language
barriers recognize that A-Eb-C-B stands for Arnold SCHoenberg (on the
basis of the Germanic spelling of the letters as A-S-C-H.)
Conversely, composers using musical tropes
to represent
non-musical objects and concepts employ a great variety of mimetic,
descriptive, suggestive, allusive, and symbolic means. Single
components (motifs or musical formulas) and their syntactic
organization, vertical texture and horizontal structure, tonal
organization and timbral coloring are entrusted with suggesting
depiction. Quotations of pre-existing musical material may add
allusive reference, and allow for modifications of context, medium,
or tonal environment that successfully express defamiliarization or
irony. Last but by no means least, countable units--from notes to
beats, bars, or sections --invite play with numerical symbols both
traditional and innovative. These latter cases move ever further into
the realm described by the phrase "the joy of literacy": not only do
such significations remain hidden to the uninitiated, we no longer
expect them to be accessible even to insiders through the means of
primary sensory perception, but only to skilled readers of the
score.
Furthermore, music, as I hope to show
convincingly, is capable of
a kind of descriptive effect that Wendy Steiner, writing about the
poetry of e.e.cummings and others, refers to as the "embodying of the
still-movement paradox." Even more than language, music can do so
without compromising its intrinsic logic. The reason for this greater
flexibility is that music, while resembling verbal texts in that it
develops in time, at the same time "paints." Like the media of visual
art, it conveys to its audience the sensual experience of
colors and textures, rather than referring to them as language
does. Both its range of register and its compositional textures
(polyphony above all) create a spatiality to which literary modes can
only allude.
6 Instrumental Music and Narrativity
But can non-texted music also narrate? In
his work on Mahler,
Anthony Newcomb (drawing on definitions by Paul Ricoeur) maintains
that it can and does. Following a work of music entails, he believes,
the same basic activity as following a story: the interpretation of a
succession of events as a meaningful configuration. Carolyn Abbate
urges us to differentiate the nineteenth-century claim that certain
linear elements of music can be regarded in analogy to the events in
a dramatic plot (music is perceived as generating expectations on the
basis of culturally established paradigms; it moves through tension
and release towards closure). She argues that music should be "seen
not merely as "acting out" or "representing" events as if it were a
sort of unscrolling and noisy tapestry that mimes actions not
visually but sonically, but also as occasionally respeaking an object
in a morally distancing act of narration."(FN10)
However, she cautions, such "moments of diegesis" are far from normal
or universal in non-texted instrumental music. Since Abbate is here
referring to music that does not, by its title, claim to be a
representation of an extra-musical reality, the allowance for
"narrative acts of music" is extremely encouraging. Non-texted music
may not be able to differentiate the details of a plotline because it
cannot establish the non-musical specifications of the characters and
props in the fictional world. But as the aesthetician Kendall Walton
in his work on the representational qualities of music confirms, mere
titles often suffice to provide this essential factual skeleton and
make music patently representational--and even narrative.
Having thus argued that music, like art and
literature, is capable
of depicting and referring to things, including things in a world
outside its own sonic realm, and that what is represented in a
pictorial, literary, or musical medium may be image or story, design
or narrative, I now turn to the more specific question how music may
represent something that does not belong to the primary reality "in
the world out there" or "in the soul in here," but has previously
been represented in a work of visual art or literature.
This leads me to a question that, I hope,
addresses the
delineation and definition of what the musical equivalent to
ekphrasis may be from a different perspective: the question whether
what we find in different cases can be described as poems or
paintings... and music? poems or paintings in music? or
poems or paintings into music? In this brief exploration I
wish to address the question how a poetic or pictorial source text
relates to--and possibly makes its way into--a musical
composition.
In order to develop pertinent categories
that may help me,
generally, to deal with the musical material in a systematic way and,
specifically, to know what to exclude and why, I turn (as I do so
often these days) to the already established methodologies in
(literary) ekphrasis.
7 Variations of Artistic Interaction
In this context, the thoughts of the
Scandinavian interarts
researcher Hans Lund, as far as we can glean them from the only work
of his that has been translated into English, Text as Picture:
Studies in the Literary Transformation of Pictures (Swedish 1982,
English 1992) prove exceedingly helpful. In his chapter "The Picture
in the Poem: A Theoretical Discussion," Lund offers a very useful
scheme of defining what stance the author of the secondary
representation (here, a poet; in our case, a composer) may be
adopting towards the work of art (here, a painting; in our case, a
painting/poem/drama) that constitutes the primary representation of
the scene or story. Lund establishes three main categories for the
relation of text to picture: combination, integration, and
transformation. (In my discussion of the equivalents in music's
relationship to the sister arts, I will further differentiate within
two of them.) Here are Lund's definitions one by one, and my own
adaptations for the field of music.
(a) Literature or Painting ... and Music
By combination I mean a coexistence, at best a
cooperation between words and pictures. It is, then, a question of a
bi-medial communication, where the media are intended to add to and
comment on each other. The old emblematic writing belongs to this
category. Here, too, are found certain works by authors traditionally
called "Doppelbegabungen" by German critics, i.e. authors who combine
and to a certain degree master the literary as well as the pictorial
medium. Examples are William Blake, Dante Gabriel Rossetti and
Günter Grass. Works which are the results of a creative
cooperation between a writer and a pictorial artist [...] are also
found here. Illustrations made afterwards to match literary texts are
not primarily a concern for literary scholars but for art historians.
|
What Lund is sketching here amounts, it
seems to me, to two
somewhat different genres in the case of musical composition: setting
and collaboration; both answer the questions put in the heading of
this chapter with "Poems or paintings and music."
Collaborations involving music as one of the key components include
works like Parade (by Cocteau + Satie
+ Massine + Picasso)
and L'histoire du soldat (Stravinsky +
Ramuz), to name only two outstanding cases here.
Collaborations with music as one component differ essentially from
transformations of a painting or poem into music, whereby a
structured entity with all its constituent parts and many layers of
message is recreated on another plane. They are excluded from this
study for two reasons. First, it is usually unclear which sign
system, if indeed any of those involved, should be considered
primary, and which constitutes the transposition. Second, one may
assume that the myriad aspects of communication, which would
otherwise be expressed within a single artistic text, are conceived
as being shared among the collaborating arts here. We are, then, not
dealing with the transformation of form and content from one artistic
representation into another, but instead with a sort of "synthetic
effect" whereby the various arts contribute the constituent parts of
a single artistic gestalt and message. In such a joint venture,
individual components complement one another but could often not
stand on their own.
Music knows few cases that correspond
directly to the phenomena of
"emblematic writing"; or the dual art work of "Doppelbegabungen." A
composer like Arnold Schoenberg, who was also a gifted artist,
nevertheless did not, to my knowledge, create any work in which
expressions of his dual talent combine in such a way as to engender a
single overarching artistic message. The closest analog in recent
music is probably Erik Satie. Many of his piano scores (see, e.g.,
Sports et Divertissements, published as facsimile) tread
a
fine line between musical score and artwork. The brief pieces are
prefaced with drawings by Charles Martin and may have been intended,
or so Satie scholars believe, to be looked at as much as performed.
From the time when emblematic writing itself blossomed, one
composition at least seems to function as a musical analog. In the
early 17th century, Michael Maier created a work under the title
Atalanta fugiens which consists of fifty musical
settings in
an imitative style accompanied by emblems and epigrams. (Also known
as "Michael Maier's alchemical emblem book," the work is specifically
intended to be appreciated "per oculis et intellectui").(FN11)
On the other hand, the field of music
encompasses compositions
that are manifestations of a combination of talents that is much
rarer than the dual aptitude for poetry and painting, composition and
painting, or music and poetry writing: synaesthesia. In
correspondence with some painters who claim to be putting on canvas
the hues communicated to them in musical sounds, composers endowed
with this gift of seeing colors when hearing pitches or chords may
purport to be creating a composition consisting of sound and color.
In the case of composers who, like Olivier Messiaen, expected his
audience to see with their inner eye the hues expressed in his
chords, the visual component is, for most of us, beyond our
perceptive abilities and thus beyond verification; these works thus
do not literally involve two media. The composer's assertion refers
to a very private reality which is not easily shared with an audience
and the details of which have to be taken at face value. In
compositions like Alexander Scriabin's Prometheus by contrast,
notated for clavier à lumières in addition to
the instruments of musical performance, the audience does enjoy a
bi-medial performance. Moreover, analysis reveals that the
correlations of sounds and colors are part of a complex system of
spiritual symbolism.
Settings of one text in another medium,
while often intriguing in
themselves, also constitute a hybrid form in comparison to the
phenomenon I am studying here. Whenever a poetic text is set as vocal
music, or a dramatic text as opera (or, for that matter, a musical
composition as ballet), the original medium is inflected
rather than transformed. Granted, in vocal music,
intonation--one of the many features of vocal language--is modified;
secondary features dependent upon or related to intonation, like
speech tempo, word spacing, etc., may be more or less effected, and
structure may occasionally be expanded by repetitions. All other
aspects of the original text, however--vocabulary and syntax,
metaphors and allusions, the mode of expression and the objects
spoken of--will characteristically remain completely untouched. The
instrumental accompaniment may be anything from servant to partner
(and, in recent times, even competitor) to the vocal part, but it is
not typically entrusted with creating a self-contained musical
transformation of as many aspects of the poetic model as possible.
Rather, we often speak of it as "supporting" the vocal line or
"painting a backdrop" for it. Such accompaniment acts as a musical
illustration of and to the poetic text. The case is somewhat
more complex when a choreographer chooses a piece of music to which
to compose a ballet. One would want to distinguish in what cases the
music is used primarily as an aesthetically satisfying vehicle for
the choreography, and in what cases it actually inspires a conceptual
interpretation.
Ideally, in order to make such a distinction
with authority, one
would need to create an artificial situation in which one could focus
on choreographies in a silent performance--as, for instance, on video
recordings without tone. The question would then be whether such a
purely kinetic work could be intuited as a transformation of
(essential aspects of) the musical compositions in any of the myriad
ways in which ekphrastic poems--often read without the model being
present--relate to the works of visual art to which they owe their
being. This brings me back to Lund and his second definition.
(b) Literature or Painting ... in Music
The second sector of my field of research I call integration.
Here a pictorial element is a part of the visual shape of a literary
work. Whereas pictorial elements in a combination have relatively
independent functions, a pictorial element in an integration cannot be
removed without destroying the verbal structure. Integration means that
verbal and visual elements constitute an overall unity which is not
reducible to the sum of the constituting elements. In this sector we
find stanzas in the shape of a goblet or hour-glass and the like in the
pattern poems of baroque poetry, as well as Apollinaire's Calligrammes
and the concrete poetry of Modernism.
|
The integration of verbal and visual
expressions into musical
compositions includes many examples that need little reflection:
neither verbal performance instructions nor the visual element of the
musical notation itself would normally prompt us to think that we are
dealing with a relationship between two art forms, although both
instances meet the condition: both will not be encountered
independently of the musical contents. Musical notation would not be
in existence without the medium it aims to perpetuate, and
compositions would not have survived --or at least not in a condition
as close to their original design--without the help of some means of
record-keeping. Similarly, performance indications detached from the
music to be performed make no sense, while music conceived with
expressive nuances that cannot be specified unequivocally outside the
verbal medium loses a valuable dimension when deprived of these
directions.
While these examples of integration hardly
concern us in the
context I have set out to examine here, there are several other cases
that would require answering our initial question with "the visual or
the verbal in music." Music knows the equivalent to "stanzas
in the shape of a goblet."(FN12) Conversely,
Kurt Schwitters's famous Ursonate and many works of Hugo Ball
have shown us that "poems in the form of musical sound patterns" are
equally possible. Then there are cases in which visual elements that
originate outside music appear integrated into a piece of music. One
example occurs in scores whose visual presentation follows shapes the
outlines of which suggest depicted objects.(FN13)
In other cases, a constituent part of the musical language is based
on a linguistic component which would not necessarily appear
independently in a poem or drama; themes shaped on the basis of
letter-name allusions (B-A-C-H etc.) fall into this category.
Finally, as if in combination of the implicit graphic aspect and the
implicit letter names, a musical score may contain elements that are
graphically both musical and verbal text. The most striking
example that comes to my mind is the title page of a composition for
male chorus written in the ghetto Terezín by one of its
inmates, the composer Pavel Haas. Besides the title itself, Al
Sifod, and the usual information regarding composer, poet--Jakov
Simoni--and scoring, Haas decorates the title page with musical notes
that, while they are carefully placed on their staves, are actually
adapted to look like Hebrew letters. The power that be in the camp
would hardly have recognized this, but the ones for whom the message
was intended did: it reads "Kizkeret lejon hasana harison vemuacharon
begalut Terezín"--In remembrance of the first and at the same
time the last anniversary of the Terezín exile.)(FN14)
One step further, musical scores may be
accompanied by verbal and
visual texts in the form of epigrams and illustrations. Since
epigrams are frequently quotations from extant literary works, they
could, of course, stand alone and do not concern us here.
Illustrations in musical manuscripts, however, form a category of
their own. Before Satie's sketches in his own pieces at the beginning
of our century, they were known primarily from manuscripts of late
medieval and Renaissance music. An illustrative example is the famous
Chansonnier Cordiforme, the "heart-shaped chansonnier." More fanciful
than useful for music making, it is a kind of troubadour song written
into a preciously illuminated heart (topped with four instead of two
semicircles). Similarly, the visual, verbal, and musical components
appear almost inseparably integrated, and the artistic ingeniously
blended with the practical, in the manuscript pages of
fifteenth-century canons.
In a four-part untexted canon by Bartolom‚
Ramos de Pareja
(c1440-1491), the single staff containing the musical sequence is
bent into a circular shape and set, in golden ink, against a
background of deep sky blue. Wind spirits blowing from the four sides
of the page into the notes indicate the entry of the four voices,
while the calligraphy fitted into the circle betrays the composer as
a music theorist, who informs singers about the modes they will
detect in the four-part harmony resulting from the proper execution
of this canon.
Opera as a genre typically relies on
integrating a verbal text
into the composition in such a way that both elements, lyrics and
music, when represented separately, seem to be lacking an essential
complement. However, the degree to which the component parts of
opera--the libretto on the one hand and the "pure" music on the
other&--are capable of also functioning independently is often
greater than in the cases Lund mentions. While the hour-glass shape
of a poem is really nothing but an empty line drawing (and usually a
fuzzy one, for that matter) once the words are taken out, the same
cannot be said for librettos. Many of them may be of the rather more
unimaginative kind when taken as dramatic works; but, as testified in
the now established term "Literaturoper," there are a number of
literary works that originated as dramas and continue to stand as
such, before and after they are used by a composer. And as, for
instance, Hindemith's symphonies Mathis der Maler and Die
Harmonie der Welt prove, even the music can sometimes function as
a fully valid artistic testimony when taken on its own. Yet these
cases are exceptions rather than the rule, and the "music alone" or
"drama alone" typically differs from the corresponding component that
forms a constituent part of the opera.
This brings me to Lund's third definition.
(c) Literature or Painting ... into Music
In the third category--which I call transformation--no
pictorial element is combined with or integrated into the verbal text.
The text refers to an element or a combination of elements in pictures
not present before the reader's eyes. The information to the reader
about the picture is given exclusively by the verbal language.
|
This, then, is the case of a poem or
painting being
transformed into music--the focus of this study. Where
transformations appear in poetry or prose on painting,
they
are referred to as ekphrasis. In music, such ekphrasis can take as
its object a work of literature (as is the case in Ravel's piano
piece Gibet, briefly described above) or a work of visual art.
Compositions that deal respectively with these two sides of musical
ekphrasis include, on the one hand, symphonic compositions on
Symbolist drama (Charles Martin Loeffler's and Bohuslav Martinu's
compositions on Maurice Maeterlinck's marionette play La mort de
Tintagiles, and Schoenberg's work on Maeterlinck's Pelleas und
Melisande) as well as musical works about poems short and long
(Schoenberg's sextet Verklärte Nacht and Elliott Carter's
transmedialization, in Concerto for Orchestra, of
Saint-John-Perse's epic poem Vents, and to a lesser degree, in
A Symphony for Three Orchestras, on Hart Crane's epos The
Bridge.(FN15) On the other hand, I
explore music on paintings: the musical "triptychs" twentieth-century
composers form from works of quattrocento artists (Ottorino
Respighi's Trittico botticelliano and Bohuslav Martinu's
Les Fresques de Piero della Francesca), two
transmedializations of a Romantic painting (Serge Rachmaninov and Max
Reger on Böcklin's Isle of the Dead), three musical
ekphrases of the same early modern work by Paul Klee (the English
composer Peter Maxwell Davies's, the American Gunther Schuller's, and
the German Giselher Klebe's compositions under the title The
Twittering Machine), and two contemporary Danish composers'
reactions to drawings by M.C. Escher (Per Norgard's Ant Fugue
from Prelude and Ant Fugue [with Crab Canon]: Hommage a
M.C. Escher and Hans Abraham's Three Worlds).
When transformation of a work of visual art
is brought onto the
theatrical stage and wedded with the miming aspect of that genre, we
speak of enactments. Here I know of at least three
compositions based on serial paintings that can be shown to contain
distinct elements of enactment. This is particularly intriguing given
the fact that neither composition is strictly theatrical in its
focus. Music knows a few cases where something corresponding to the
typical dual transformation--from the visual to the verbal to the
mimed--occurs outside the opera. However, since the operatic
environment is the characteristic one for this sub-genre, I would
like to introduce musical enactment using as an example the three
scenes from act VI ("Sechstes Bild") of Hindemith's opera Mathis
der Maler.
In the first of these scenes, Hindemith's
painter Mathis attempts
to soothe the distraught young girl Regina with a narration of what
he claims to see in a picture portraying three angels. His verbal
depiction leads us to one of the second-tier panels of the
Isenheim Altarpiece, the masterpiece of the operatic
protagonist's historical model, Grünewald. At this juncture,
Hindemith the librettist puts into the mouth of his character Mathis
a most intriguing tripartite description and interpretation of the
panel that the historical "Master Mathis" painted ten or more years
prior to the year into which this fictional conversation is placed.
In the way in which Mathis tells Regina about the "pious pictures,"
no mention is made of who created them; the narration appears guided
by the idea and intention of what is portrayed rather than by an
attempt to describe the visual composition in all its details. Mathis
focuses on the spiritual aspect of this concert--and so does the
music in which Hindemith sets this scene.
This "narrated portrayal" of the "Angelic
Concert" is complemented
in the scene that follows by an enactment combined with a narration
of one of the two rear panels, "The Temptation of Saint Antony." The
events presented on stage function on three levels. First, in the
larger context of the operatic plot, Mathis's encounter with human
tempters and monstrous tormentors appears like a bad dream--or a
vision, given that he perceives himself as the Egyptian hermit
Antony. Second, the verbal onslaught by the seven human tempters
functions as a multi-layered interpretative embodiment of what is,
beyond the reference to the pictorial representation in the altar
panel, both the inner story of the temptations of Saint Antony and a
dramatic portrayal of the plight in which Mathis is caught. Third,
the physical attack by the monsters is at the same time a tableau
vivant of Grünewald's depiction and its musical
transmedialization: the choir does not only accompany with insults
and spiteful interpretations the assault by hellish monsters to which
Mathis/Antony is subjected in the center of the stage, but
simultaneously narrates the scene as painted by Grünewald. All
images evoked in this scene also reflect a deeper spiritual meaning
since they can be understood as provocations, as torments that emerge
from the victim's own doubting mind. They represent his spiritual
nightmares and the internal enemies that haunt his soul.
The third scene in this sequence, entitled
"The Visit of Saint
Antony in the Hermitage of Saint Paul" after the Grünewald panel
to which it relates, limits the enactment to the visual recreation:
stage design, costumes, posture and position of the two actors. No
narrative relates what we see and hear to the painting, thus allowing
us to focus all the more on the symbolic significance of the
scene.
The older hermit Paul ("embodied" by the
operatic character,
Cardinal Albrecht) acts as a spiritual adviser to Antony
(= Mathis). While his verbal admonitions deal
unequivocally with the reality of the artist in the time of the
Lutheran Uprising and the Peasants' War, the scenic setting binds the
conversation into the larger conflict of conscience that is, both
literally and figuratively, through the ekphrasis of the altar
panels, the subject matter of the opera. Hindemith's music adds a
wealth of nuances that corroborate and enhance this interpretive
layering.
Another fascinating case of such mediated
enactment of a pictorial
narrative exists in Stravinsky's opera The Rake's Progress.
The stimulus here is a series of eight engravings etched in 1735 by
William Hogarth, after an equal number of paintings he had completed
a year earlier. Stravinsky, inspired by these prints, followed Aldous
Huxley's recommendation to ask Auden for a libretto dramatizing the
story told in the etchings, on which he could then base his opera.
Auden accepted and, with the help of Chester Kallman, told the story
of the rake in a style that aimed at once (I quote Williard
Spiegelman) "to recapture the myths and language of an earlier, more
optimistic world, and to examine that world from the perspective of
our own.... the libretto is Auden's attempt to adapt certain poetic
styles to the conditions of twentieth-century literary life, to
imitate or parody older models in much the same way that Stravinsky's
music casts new light on earlier operatic techniques."
However, what sets this case of musical
enactment of a pictorial
source apart from the two texted examples I will be examining as part
of my study is the fact that the Auden/Kallman libretto is a literary
ekphrasis in itself, of which Stravinsky's music then gives a
setting. By contrast, the texts Honegger uses for his oratorio La
danse des mort on Holbeinis Totentanz, while "authored" by
Paul Claudel, are actually compiled from the Bible. As such they
constitute something akin to a verbal embodiment of the common source
that inspired the artist and the composer, rather than Claudel's
ekphrastic reaction to Holbein's artistic rendering. The situation is
very similar in the case of Janacek's composition on Josef
Kresz-Mecina's panels The Lord's Prayer which the composer
based on five tableaux vivants he had devised himself. Here,
too, the text predates both the art and its musical
transmedialization.
Compositions based on ekphrastic
poems--poems that are themselves
transformations of pictorial texts--while often charming, are least
pertinent to the aims of my study. They are usually little more than
mere settings. Francis Poulenc's songs on Guillaume Apollinaire's
Le bestiaire, whose poems are in turn based on woodcuts
by
Raoul Dufy, fall into this category. So do Poulenc's settings of Paul
Éluard's poems Travail du peintre, which verbally
represent the style and characteristics of various contemporary
painters, and Reynaldo Hahn's similarly motivated Portraits de
peintres after poems by Marcel Proust. Poulenc also set
Apollinaire's Calligrammes, which are not "poems on pictures"
but rather "poems in the form of pictures"--a feature that is by
necessity lost once the text, now used as "lyrics" for songs, is
fitted between the staves of musical notation. At the other end of
the spectrum, verbal ekphrasis may indeed stimulate further musical
ekphrasis in an independent musical work. Thus Debussy's piano piece
Clair de lune in Suite Bergamasque was
apparently
inspired by Paul Verlaine's ekphrastic poem (by the same title) after
Antoine Watteau's painting, Fêtes galantes.
Finally, the composer's interest in a
musical transformation of a
given work of verbal or pictorial art may inspire a creative artist
working in yet another medium to expand the ekphrastic process even
further, adding yet another transformation. The cases of dual
transmedialization I am most eager to examine are those involving
three different media each: from the pictorial to the verbal
and on to the musical, from the pictorial to the kinetic on to the
musical, or from the poetic model to the musical transformation to
the visual or kinetic interpretation. Detailed analyses exploring two
examples for this kind of multimedial "fate" in interarts space of an
original work will conclude my case studies.
8 Central Questions in Research on
Musical
Ekphrasis
The central questions I will be asking
regard the scope and nature
of this interartistic, intersemiotic transmedialization and can be
summed up as follows:
*
|
What choices do individual composers make in their
quest musically to transmedialize a pictorial or literary
representation?
|
*
|
Do the choices made by the composers of a certain
historical and cultural context allow to distinguish and describe a
newly emerging "convention" of intersemiotic transformation?
|
*
|
Does the range of stances adopted by composers to
works of literature or visual art parallel those observed in ekphrastic
poets?
|